Piazza Class page.
Week 4: 5 February 2018.
- Opening Remarks:
The reading is a bit light this week; I am giving you some space to read your book for the book
review, and write the review.
- Reading:
-
Chapters 3 and 4 of Stillwell. (The past week from Bell remains relevant here).
- Assignment: Due Monday, February 12. (HW 5)
It is OK to discuss this among yourselves. We all have something to learn from each other.
To hand in: Email a .pdf to Mehrzad Monzavi
Mehrzad@math.tamu.edu.
-
I've always been a fan of perfect numbers.
Give the defining property of a perfect number.
Prove that if 2n-1 is a prime number, p, then 2n-1p is a perfect number.
Write down four perfect numbers. Bonus: How many perfect numbers are there?
-
Continued fractions are somewhat of a lost art.
It is known, for example, that the truncations of a continued fraction for a real number α are the best rational approximations to α.
Do all four exercises in Section 3.4 of Stillwell.
-
Consider Archimedes' quote from The Method: "It is of course easier to supply the proof when we have previously acquired some
knowledge of the questions by the method, than it is to find it without any previous knowledge."
What was "the method" he is referring to?
What does his quote say about the role of experimentation or studying examples in Mathematics?
-
Archimedes' use of exhaustion to determine areas predated the Calculus by over 1800 years.
Try your hand at this method by doing the exercises in Stillwell's Section 4.4 to prove the
formula for the logarithm of product of rational numbers.
Make sure to use exhaustion and not calculus tricks.
Why did I restrict to your showing the formula for rational numbers?
This is challenging. Do discuss it on Piazza. Let me provide you with a strong hint.
Suppose that you want to prove that a particular region R has particular number A as its area.
For this, you consider lower- and upper- approximations of the area of R.
In this case, you use rectangles (Riemann sums) to get the lower and upper approximations.
Now here is where the logic of the method of exhaustion comes in.
You show that for any number L less than A, there is a lower approximation whose rectangles' areas add up to a number exceeding
L, and the same mutatis mutandis for any number G greater than A.
This shows that the area of R is A, and it is not by an infinitary process.
I like to think of this method in the following way:
To show a number (e.g. the area of R) is some area A, is to show that it cannot be less than A and that it cannot be greater
than A.
Contrast this to the Calculus, where you have Riemann sums that are not necessarily lower or upper approximations to the region R, but we
have that the values of the Riemann sums converge to some number.
In (this modern vierw of The Calculus), we do not need to know A, we find A in taking the integral, using Newton's Fundamental
Theorem of Calculus.
What makes The Calculus better—and this is what I teach, particularly in Calculus 3—is that by approximating some quantity (say flux
across a membrane, or surfaces area, or aggregrate gravitational attraction, or ....) by Riemann sums which converge to some value, we
have not only given a way to calculate the quantity we want, but, and this is important, actually defined that quantity.
Think about this. What is the length of a curve that is not made up of arcs of circles or line segments?
The only reasonable and rigorous definition is as the limit of approximating polygons (collections of line segments) or arcs of circles.
The same is true for other quantities in Science.
Back to the question you were asked.
From the definition of exhaustion, to show two things are equal, say log(a) and log(ab)-log(b), is to show how any lower
approximation to one can be transformed into a lower approximation for the other, with the same area, and the same for upper approximations.
(Note that, as a mathematician, I use log for the logarithm with respect to the natural base, Euler's number e.)
Last modified: Mon Feb 5 21:01:08 CST 2018